Preorder

In mathematics, especially in order theory, preorders are binary relations that are reflexive and transitive.

For example, all partial orders and equivalence relations are preorders. The name quasi-order is also common for preorders.

Many order theoretical definitions for partially ordered sets can be generalized to preorders, but the extra effort of generalization is rarely needed.

Contents

Formal definition

Consider some set P and a binary relation ≤ on P. Then ≤ is a preorder, or quasiorder, if it is reflexive and transitive, i.e., for all a, b and c in P, we have that:

aa (reflexivity)
if ab and bc then ac (transitivity)

Note that an alternate definition of preorder requires the relation to be irreflexive. However, as this article is examining preorders as a logical extension of partial orders, the current definition is more intuitive.

A set that is equipped with a preorder is called a preordered set.

If a preorder is also antisymmetric, that is, ab and ba implies a = b, then it is a partial order.

On the other hand, if it is symmetric, that is, if ab implies ba, then it is an equivalence relation.

A preorder which is preserved in all contexts (i.e. respected by all functions on P) is called a precongruence. A precongruence which is also symmetric (i.e. is an equivalence relation) is a congruence relation.

Equivalently, a preorder on the set P can be defined as a category with object set P where every homset has at most one element (one for objects which are related, zero otherwise).

Examples of preorders

In computer science, one can find examples of the following preorders.

Example of a total preorder:

Constructions

Every binary relation R on a set S can be extended to a preorder on S by taking the transitive closure and reflexive closure, R+=. The transitive closure indicates path connection in R: x R+ y if and only if there is an R-path from x to y.

Given a preorder \lesssim on S one may define an equivalence relation ~ on S such that a ~ b if and only if a \lesssim b and b \lesssim a. (The resulting relation is reflexive since a preorder is reflexive, transitive by applying transitivity of the preorder twice, and symmetric by definition.)

Using this relation, it is possible to construct a partial order on the quotient set of the equivalence, S / ~, the set of all equivalence classes of ~. Note that if the preorder is R+=, S / ~ is the set of R-cycle equivalence classes: x ∈ [y] if and only if x = y or x is in an R-cycle with y. In any case, on S / ~ we can define [x] ≤ [y] if and only if x \lesssim y. By the construction of ~ , this definition is independent of the chosen representatives and the corresponding relation is indeed well-defined. It is readily verified that this yields a partially ordered set.

Conversely, from a partial order on a partition of a set S one can construct a preorder on S. There is a 1-to-1 correspondence between preorders and pairs (partition, partial order).

For a preorder "\lesssim", a relation "<" can be defined as a < b if and only if (a \lesssim b and not b \lesssim a), or equivalently, using the equivalence relation introduced above, (a \lesssim b and not a ~ b). It is a strict partial order; every strict partial order can be the result of such a construction. If the preorder is anti-symmetric, hence a partial order "≤", the equivalence is equality, so the relation "<" can also be defined as a < b if and only if (ab and ab).

(Alternatively, for a preorder "\lesssim", a relation "<" can be defined as a < b if and only if (a \lesssim b and ab). The result is the reflexive reduction of the preorder. However, if the preorder is not anti-symmetric the result is not transitive, and if it is, as we have seen, it is the same as before.)

Conversely we have a \lesssim b if and only if a < b or a ~ b. This is the reason for using the notation "\lesssim"; "≤" can be confusing for a preorder that is not anti-symmetric, it may suggest that ab implies that a < b or a = b.

Note that with this construction multiple preorders "\lesssim" can give the same relation "<", so without more information, such as the equivalence relation, "\lesssim" cannot be reconstructed from "<". Possible preorders include the following:

Number of preorders

Number of n-element binary relations of different types
n all transitive reflexive preorder partial order total preorder total order equivalence relation
0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
1 2 2 1 1 1 1 1 1
2 16 13 4 4 3 3 2 2
3 512 171 64 29 19 13 6 5
4 65536 3994 4096 355 219 75 24 15
OEIS A002416 A006905 A053763 A000798 A001035 A000670 A000142 A000110

As explained above, there is a 1-to-1 correspondence between preorders and pairs (partition, partial order). Thus the number of preorders is the sum of the number of partial orders on every partition. For example:

i.e. together 29 preorders.
i.e. together 355 preorders.

Interval

For a \lesssim b, the interval [a,b] is the set of points x satisfying a \lesssim x and x \lesssim b, also written a \lesssim x \lesssim b. It contains at least the points a and b. One may choose to extend the definition to all pairs (a,b). The extra intervals are all empty.

Using the corresponding strict relation "<", one can also define the interval (a,b) as the set of points x satisfying a < x and x < b, also written a < x < b. An open interval may be empty even if a < b.

Also [a,b) and (a,b] can be defined similarly.

See also

References

  • Schröder, Bernd S. W. (2002), Ordered Sets: An Introduction, Boston: Birkhäuser, ISBN 0-8176-4128-9